The philosopher Peter Boghossian recently tweeted something that set me musing on whether it is possible for one false belief to be ‘better’ than another.
As a result, I decided to re-up these ruminations, which were inspired by a similar debate, in letter form, on the nature of belief between Boghossian and the Belgian philosopher Maarten Boudry. The debate itself Peter’s side of the debate is no longer available publicly, but I quote most of the key points here, so you should be able to follow the relevant parts of their argument easily. You can read Maarten’s arguments here. The piece is adapted from an article that first appeared in Areo Magazine. You can read the original here.
What do we mean when we say we believe something—as opposed to hoping, fearing, suspecting, imagining or entertaining the notion as a fantasy? One common definition is that belief involves commitment. Carl Ginet writes that, when you believe a proposition p, you “count on its being the case that p,” you are willing to stake something on that assumption and are “dismissive or complacent … toward the possibility of … its turning out that not-p.” He provides the example of someone who, halfway into a long car journey, suddenly wonders whether he locked his front door before leaving. He believes he did and therefore decides not to turn back—risking the possibility that the door is open and he will be robbed. We can assess a person’s beliefs, then, by asking what do her actions imply that she assumes to be true? (This is why John Hickenlooper famously drank a glass of fracking fluid to prove that he believed it to be safe.)
Pamela Hieronymi describes this commitment in terms of arguments, rather than actions. It involves a willingness to be “answerable to certain questions and criticisms,” able, as Jon Rosen puts it, “to confidently defend my view with a set of arguments.” These arguments must make sense to you personally, i.e., as Gray Maddrey describes it here, you must be prepared to answer the question “what reason do you have for choosing?”—even if only to yourself.
Richard Dawkins’ analogy of memes may help here. Beliefs are memes that “aim” (figuratively) to gain traction within our minds, so that we can propagate them, by influencing others. To believe something, we must be convinced it meets certain requirements. We cannot believe at random. Faced with a potential belief, we are like employers sizing up candidates. Perhaps we would love to work with a particular applicant but, unfortunately, we cannot hire her because—for example—she is not a resident of our country and we are not permitted to employ non-residents. The equivalent of residency would be the belief’s compatibility with our internal, previously established criteria for determining whether or not something is true.
How Can You Make Yourself Believe Something?
To think that we can choose our beliefs implies a fundamental assumption that we possess meaningful free will. This is a topic beyond the scope of this piece, so, for the sake of argument here, I’ll simply assume that we do and that at least some of our actions are under our complete control. But is forming a belief about something one of those actions?
Philosophers distinguish between direct and indirect voluntary control. We have direct control over actions that we can perform instantly, competently, at will. For example, if you are able bodied, you can choose to stand on your tiptoes right now. But if you attempt a double pirouette en passé, you will probably wobble and fall. You could, however, begin daily ballet classes tomorrow and, eventually, you will probably be able to execute pirouettes with ease: this is indirect voluntary control. You choose to take an action now (go to ballet class) in order to produce an effect (pirouetting) in the future.
Direct doxastic voluntarism—direct control over your beliefs—implies that you can consciously choose to believe something right now. Indirect doxastic voluntarism means that you can begin to research, investigate and weigh up the opinions, which will probably lead you to change your beliefs in the future. You might, for example, wish to discard negative beliefs about yourself: that you are worthless, a failure, unlovable, etc. You probably cannot do this directly and instantly: but you can sign up for cognitive behavioural therapy (CBT), which is designed to demonstrate that those beliefs about your worth and potential for happiness are erroneous.
The problem is not just that results are not guaranteed—in either case—but that even this indirect form of control is only likely to work in very specific circumstances. CBT deals with subjective evaluations, which are more closely allied to feelings and attitudes than to beliefs. I can choose to feel pride that I am able to dance a pirouette; or ashamed that it is not that elegant because I don’t practise enough. There is wiggle room there because we are notoriously bad at judging ourselves—and, crucially, I am aware of this. Both Dunning-Krueger and its opposite, impostor syndrome, are well known phenomena. Facts are less malleable. I cannot choose to believe I am the prima ballerina at the Bolshoi.
In addition, while there is a strong, direct correlation between practising and gaining skill in ballet, there is none between researching a topic and forming a belief. This is why scholars who have dedicated their lives to complex subjects often still disagree fiercely among themselves. Research may cause you to believe something that appeared counterintuitive at first glance, when presented with watertight proof. But only if you encounter such evidence and it convinces you. A deep dive into, for example, 9/11 truther theories or homeopathy—or, indeed, the notion of doxastic voluntarism itself—may even leave you less convinced than before. You may never be able to persuade yourself that the world is flat or that leprechauns exist by sheer dint of effort.
Philosophers disagree, however, on whether any belief can be consciously chosen. As Bernard Williams explains: “With regard to no belief could I know—or … in full consciousness, even suspect—that I had acquired it at will.” If I am cognisant that the only reason I believe x is because I arbitrarily decided to, then I also know that I have no strong reasons for believing x. I therefore don’t believe x: I just think it sounds like a nice idea. For example, I hope Homo sapiens is not the only higher order sentient species in the universe. But, in the absence of convincing proof either way, I cannot form a belief that aliens exist, no matter how much I long for First Contact.
Jonathan Bennett suggests a solution to this seeming impossibility in a thought experiment involving a society of amnesiac voluntary believers:
Credam is a community each of whose members can be immediately induced to acquire beliefs. It doesn’t happen often, because they don’t often think: “I don’t believe that p, but it would be good if I did.” Still, such thoughts come to them occasionally, and on some of those occasions the person succumbs to temptation and wills himself to have the desired belief. … When a Credamite gets a belief in this way, he forgets that this is how he came by it. The belief is always one that he has entertained and has thought to have some evidence in its favour; though in the past he has rated the counter-evidence more highly … [now] he wills himself to find the other side more probable. After succeeding, he forgets that he willed himself to do it.
Credam, clearly, is planet Earth. We are all susceptible to confirmation bias and wishful thinking. The examples that support the conclusion we wish to draw spring more readily to mind, the evidence that confirms it seems more weighty. We overestimate our own rationality whenever our emotions are involved. In The Happiness Hypothesis, Jonathan Haidt describes reason as the rider perched atop the elephant of emotion:
I [am] a rider on the back of an elephant. I’m holding the reins in my hands, and by pulling one way or the other I can tell the elephant to turn, to stop, or to go. I can direct things, but only when the elephant doesn’t have desires of his own. When the elephant really wants to do something, I’m no match for him.
However, this does not mean that we can decide what we believe. In Haidt’s vision, we don’t deliberately choose our beliefs to suit our feelings: we are swayed towards specific beliefs by those feelings without our knowledge—and even against our will (when trying to discover what is objectively true, we cannot help being influenced by our emotions). Often, I think I am guiding the elephant—but in fact I am an incompetent mahout, astride a beast who is lumbering off in whatever direction he pleases. I’m lucky he hasn’t unseated me altogether.
At other times, however, I would love to simply be carried along for the ride, but I can feel reason taking hold of the reins against my wishes. This is the phenomenon we know as cognitive dissonance, when we cling to beliefs that are convenient or flattering, even as it begins to dawn on us that they are false. We attempt to deny the truth, we protest too much, we want to be lulled by a comforting delusion but it usually proves impossible. This can lead, at best, to pesky niggling doubts. If those doubts shake our fundamental worldview, they can cause existential despair. “Humankind,” as T. S. Eliot warns, “cannot bear too much reality.” Gerard Manley Hopkins vividly describes his own crisis of faith:
No worst, there is none. Pitched past pitch of grief,
More pangs will, schooled at forepangs, wilder wring.
Comforter, where, where is your comforting?
Mary, mother of us, where is your relief?
My cries heave, herds-long; huddle in a main, a chief
Woe, world-sorrow; on an age-old anvil wince and sing
—Then lull, then leave off. Fury had shrieked “No ling-
ering! Let me be fell: force I must be brief.”O the mind, mind has mountains; cliffs of fall
Frightful, sheer, no-man-fathomed. Hold them cheap
May who ne’er hung there. Nor does long our small
Durance deal with that steep or deep. Here! creep,
Wretch, under a comfort serves in a whirlwind: all
Life death does end and each day dies with sleep.
If we had a choice as to what to believe, who would choose that?
However, the philosopher Peter Boghossian has argued that, under certain circumstances, voluntary beliefs is possible.
Religious Belief
Boghossian first began to question whether belief is always involuntary when a devout Christian student told him “that he chose to not believe in the Neanderthals” because their existence contradicts the Genesis creation story. In response to Boghossian, Maarten Boudry argues—and I agree—that the student was simply weighing up two mutually incompatible sources of evidence and deciding to credit one over the other. If you believe the Bible is literally true, it is rational to regard any evidence that seems to contradict it as fabricated. Belief in the Bible itself is not voluntary, as Boudry points out: “People cannot simply choose to believe that some book is the Word of God. Even with a gun put against your head, you couldn’t bring ourselves to believe something like that, through sheer willpower.” This highlights an ethical problem at the core of most religions: they demand genuine belief in a god or gods (not just lip service and ritual observance, which, on its own, may even be considered hypocritical). If belief is not a choice, this is an impossible demand.
To many lifelong atheists, the phenomenon of religious (here, Christian) belief is difficult to fathom. Belief in miracles is especially hard to explain. As David Hume recognised, such belief is based on arguments from authority: priests report it as true and ask us to take it on trust; this trust is derived in turn from the testimony of a very old book (Genesis), whose author is unknown and which contains assertions that contradict the laws of nature. Hume concludes that it should be impossible to believe an account of this kind: “no testimony is sufficient to establish a miracle, unless the testimony be of such a kind, that its falsehood would be more miraculous, than the fact, which it endeavours to establish.” This leaves us with a puzzle: how do people believe in talking snakes, seven-day creations etc.? Our inability to answer this need not mean, however, that believers simply opt for belief voluntarily. Those who have had religious epiphanies generally do not describe them in terms of willpower: they see themselves as the lucky passive recipients of revelation and as having entered into a relationship with something or someone else that exists out there, independent of them.
Wishful Thinking
Boghossian’s second example of voluntary belief is drawn from Aesop’s fable of the fox who, frustrated by grapes that are just out of his reach, “walked away with his nose in the air, saying: ‘I am sure they are sour.’” In cases of unrequited love, Boghossian suggests, “the same principle is sometimes at play” when the jilted person asserts “I’m too good for her anyway.” This may be simply posturing and bravado. But if it is a case of a real change of mind, is it a type of deliberate wishful thinking?
Maarten Boudry counters this by asking, “is it true that, at least some of the time, people can simply choose to believe something because it’s comforting to them, alleviating their guilt, boosting their self-esteem?” Under two circumstances, he suggests, we have some partial control: if the belief concerns something patently subjective, or if there is a “certain ring of plausibility” to our interpretation. The protestations of both the fox and the rejected lover are assessments of how they feel about their failures to achieve their goals, masquerading as judgements about the objects of their desire (grapes and girl). And, as Boudry explains, “internal psychological states are somewhat ambiguous and open to self-manipulation.” How we feel is ever changing and hard to pin down: we can sometimes convince ourselves to feel differently both because it is so often impossible to define our current emotions and because, given several plausible possibilities, our feelings are influenced by which we choose to concentrate on. As Jon Rosen explains, “one can also exercise one’s epistemic freedom insofar as one can suspend judgment on a given matter and then decide where or how to focus one’s attention on items of evidence.”
Some of Boghossian’s other examples illustrate how we can deliberately adopt a specific focus. Seasoned MMA fighters “often convince themselves that they will win—even if, or maybe even especially if, they’re fighting against odds.” A torture victim trapped in a dungeon can, Boghossian argues, persuade himself that help is on its way. The mother of a dead child can believe that her daughter is now in heaven. In all these cases, people are faced with two scenarios, both of which are possible—though not equally probable. We boost our confidence, stave off despair, comfort ourselves by fixing our attention on the better of the two. In this murky psychological terrain, a combination of intense hope and stubborn focus can stand in for certainty, but it is not identical to unequivocal belief. Doubt always remains. A fighter who truly considered himself invulnerable would underestimate his opponents and be easily beaten. A mother who really felt her child was in a happier place would not mourn her with such intensity.
Boghossian highlights two other cases of wishful thinking. The first, borrowed from Carl Ginet, is that of the man who decides to believe, halfway through a long road trip, that he did lock his front door before leaving. This is perhaps simpler than it appears. Most of us have routines we carry out before leaving for a trip. Habits of this kind often run on autopilot and we know that, in such cases, not having a conscious memory of having performed an action does not mean we failed to carry it out. If your conscious mind is focused on the article you need to write or on the argument you had with your boyfriend last night, you may reach work with no clear memory of the drive: no recollection of having flipped on your indicator light and looked in the side mirror and over your shoulder before changing lanes on the motorway, or of having braked and shifted down a gear as you took that last corner. We rely on procedural memory—and it is usually safe to do so. Ginet’s traveller knows that he probably locked the door, and that kind of knowledge is enough to stave off anxiety most of the time, in all but the most neurotic.
The second case Boghossian presents is that of “choosing not to believe something about someone when you’re in love with them”: specifically, a husband may refuse to believe that his wife is having an affair, despite all the tell-tale signs. This is also about a weighing up of probabilities: your wife’s trustworthiness against that unexplained credit card bill you found. We are extremely bad at accurate assessment when we are emotionally invested in a result. Depending on personality type, we can err on the side of credulity or paranoia.
We do not always simply choose the belief that would be most comforting and refuse to investigate further. The jealous husband roots through his wife’s handbag. The mother of the abducted child could find closure if she knew her daughter were dead. The cancer patient begs his doctor to be honest with him. This is unsurprising. It is impossible to firmly hold a belief if you know there is easily available evidence that might disprove it. Ignorance may be bliss, but only when you don’t know that you could dispel it at any time. Wishful thinking is only effective when we are able to trick ourselves. As Boudry puts it, “The second condition for successful ‘wishful thinking’ is that you should not be aware that you’re about to engage in wishful thinking. A wish can only spawn a belief if it’s working its magic just outside your conscious attention.”
Make-Believe
There is a special case in which we can comfortably entertain beliefs, while certain they are false: through what is tellingly called make-believe. We can participate in this actively—by playacting, telling stories or fantasising—or more passively—by watching a favourite Netflix series, for example—and even involuntarily—through dreams. Our emotional investment in such fictions can be so huge that they may at times prompt more intense feelings than real life. Noting that his mistress is unmoved by his devotion, but weeps over a story, Astrophil urges Stella to
think, my Dear! that you in me do read
Of lovers’ ruin, some sad tragedy.
I am not I, pity the tale of me!
We try to heighten the illusion: we avoid spoilers, as if the fictional story were unfolding in real time; we discuss the fates of characters after the book has finished, as if they existed outside its pages; we talk about actors as if they turned into their characters: Rose Leslie is a wilding from beyond The Wall; Jim Carter is a butler; Tom Cruise is a pilot. But this is crucially distinct from literal belief. Even children at play know that their games are not real, as Golomb and Kuersten’s experiments have shown. Kids who were baking with Play-Doh were astonished when a researcher took a real bite out of one of the pretend cookies.
We treat these worlds of our own creation as if they were real, even when they involve the far-fetched or the supernatural. A young wizard feels like one of us; we cry over the death of a hermaphrodite on a distant ice planet. How precisely this works is unknown. Coleridge’s famous description makes our emotions sound like a fund we can dip into, fungible as money, something we can lend a fiction to allow it to purchase what it needs to seem real. He writes that we
transfer from our inward nature a human interest and a semblance of truth sufficient to procure for these shadows of imagination that willing suspension of disbelief for the moment, which constitutes poetic faith.
Unless we are suffering from a severe mental illness, however, we never lose our grip on reality—which is how we are able to enjoy fictional depictions of even horrifying events. Samuel Johnson describes this vividly:
[Drama] is credited, whenever it moves, as a just picture of a real original; as representing to the auditor what he would himself feel, if he were to do or suffer what is there feigned to be suffered or to be done. The reflection that strikes the heart is not, that the evils before us are real evils, but that they are evils to which we ourselves may be exposed. If there be any fallacy, it is not that we fancy the players, but that we fancy ourselves unhappy for a moment; but we rather lament the possibility than suppose the presence of misery, as a mother weeps over her babe, when she remembers that death may take it from her. The delight of tragedy proceeds from our consciousness of fiction; if we thought murders and treasons real, they would please no more.
When producing and consuming fiction, we manipulate our beliefs freely, consciously and at will. This is perhaps one of the main reasons we relish it so much. But this is the only time we are able to do so.
Facts Don’t Care About Your Feelings
Boghossian lists a number of circumstances that facilitate believing something we know to be untrue. He argues that this is easier if the beliefs are “deeply validating (healthy at any size), or profoundly alleviating (profession of white guilt).” In addition,
Thinking oneself into believing that something is true is far easier when others believe it, when one thinks one is a better person for holding the belief, and when loneliness or social acceptance are consequences for either denying or professing belief.
These are excellent reasons to pretend to hold or wish to hold a belief. Daniel Dennett describes the phenomenon of approving of a belief to which one does not actually subscribe as belief in belief and cautions that it is very difficult to tell apart from the real thing:
the actions motivated by believing in belief (while not actually believing …) are … well-nigh indistinguishable from the actions of genuine believers: say the prayers, sing the hymns, tithe, proclaim one’s allegiance, volunteer for church projects, and so on. Sometimes I wonder if even 10% of the people who proclaim their belief in God actually do believe in God.
This does not just apply to faith in God. People may feign belief in a political ideology in order to be accepted by a group or stubbornly repeat confidence-boosting mantras at the bathroom mirror in a vain attempt to feel better about the 10 kilos they’ve gained. But these extrinsic reasons for believing something, as Pamela Hieronymi calls them, are not persuasive: “you will not, by finding convincing reasons that you take only to show that believing p is worth doing, therein become committed to the truth of p.” It would be nice if x were true is not a cogent argument for the truth of x.
Why can I not be persuaded to believe something by the argument that it would benefit me to believe it? Because there is an external reality out there and that reality is unaffected by my wishes, hopes and dreams. The universe is not arranged to suit my personal convenience. Whether something is true is quite independent of whether I would like it to be. Humans have always resorted to magical thinking and superstition in times of desperation in an attempt to convince ourselves that we can exercise control over our unpredictable world—but, most of the time, most of us know we cannot.
This is almost certainly the result of our evolution. As Oliver Traldi has argued in conversation with me, Jordan Peterson is wrong in his hypothesis that there is a Darwinian truth, which differs from reality and instead constitutes “whatever is useful to us.” There is no biological advantage to being delusional. As Boudry points out, if you were to don a pair of the Joo Janta 200 Super-Chromatic Peril Sensitive Sunglasses, described in The Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy, which turn opaque in the presence of danger, you would not last long. It’s a rough universe out there.
As Boudry explains, “Evolution doesn’t care about our sense of comfort. It wants us to pay attention to reality, even (I’d say especially) when reality is terrifying.” Even at play, we do not deactivate what Neil van Leeuwen calls our “continual reality tracking”—for good reason. “One’s factual belief that no hyenas are near must vanish on seeing fresh hyena tracks, on pain of being lunch.”
Ultimately, then, our ability to control what we believe is very limited. And this is a good thing. It ensures our survival and flourishing. As Boudry argues here, “we all need comfortable illusions to get by … [but] Sooner or later, they will collide with reality because reality couldn’t give a damn about your illusions.”